On Justification and Argumentation
In a previous post, I wrote about abortion, which of course received some amount of pushback. However, I also got pushback from an unexpected direction. A number of commenters pushed back against trying to get more complete justifications for their beliefs.
Bsycho for instance says:
Does it harm the life or liberty of the uninvolved party?
If the answer is “no”, then the uninvolved party can fish off. Period
And when pushed as to why this is the case, answers:
Because harm to them is the only legitimate criteria by which they have any standing whatsoever to care. Without harm they’re just throwing a hissy fit because the world isn’t conforming to their personal aesthetic tastes. A society attempting to accommodate such people is flushing freedom down the toilet.
I don’t see how Rawls changes anything here. If you’re A, you have the right to do whatever you wish with consenting adults; if you’re B, you have that same right. If you’re B and you whine because you don’t get to block A, then you’re confusing liberty with obedience.
Charitably interpreted, I think that bsycho believes that his answer is sufficient to answer my question. Unfortunately, I disagree with him. One minor quibble is about whether the characterisation he provides is true. After all, we can cash out both sides in terms of liberty. One can on the one hand be free from being enslaved, or on the other hand be free to keep slaves. In cases of conflicting freedoms like this, it is important to explain why the freedom from enslavement trumps freedom to keep slaves. However, the key point of disagreement here is that the argument he gave is not sufficient. I can still ask why we should care about liberty instead of obedience. i.e. there is a problem of how to stop the sceptical regress.
I’ll try here to show why not being able to stop the sceptical regress can be problematic. When we do these kinds of things e.g. saying that we should legalise X or have this kind of policy and someone disagrees, presumably, the ensuing conversation is aimed at finding out who is right or wrong, or maybe showing why you are right and the other person is wrong (if there is a distinction to be made between the two ends). Productive conversations therefore contain arguments which feature reasons. Insofar as the aim is merely to convince, you start out from premises your interlocutors will agree with and from there proceed to make your argument. After all, if your interlocutors cannot even agree with your initial premises, then even if the logic of your argument is valid, how can you expect to convince them of said conclusions?
That is not all though. Just because you and your interlocutors agree on the premises, it does not follow that your premises are true. There is a certain futile aspect to arguing for a position without caring whether or not your premises are true. (What is the point of trying to convince someone if you do not think your position is true?) In certain ways then,
Nevertheless, people still seem to disagree even when they share the same premises. This disagreement is due to them drawing different conclusions from the same premises. The problem with this is that if two conclusions can be equally reasonably drawn from the same premises, then the premises in under-determine the conclusion in such a way that neither of the conclusions in question can be said to be drawn from the premises. (Though a weaker more general conclusion which is consistent with both of the former conclusions may still be said to be drawn)
For example, two people may differ on what the results of choice in the original position are in that one person says endorses Rawls’s 2 principles of justice in their entirety while another believes that something other than the difference principle would be chosen (e.g. Twin Rawls vs Real Rawls). However, even if we consider that both are equally and maximally reasonable, it does not follow that no conclusions may be drawn from the original position, only that any conclusions that could be reasonably drawn would have to be so general as to accommodate both views. (That is assuming that both are supposedly equally reasonable views) This means that in order to argue for one conclusion over another, you must show that the connection between your conclusion and the premises are stronger than that between your interlocutor’s conclusions and the shared premises. Judgements about these can get complicated, but we can make a few simplifications. Whatever else may be true, deductive arguments provide the strongest connection between premises and conclusions. The conclusion of a valid deductive argument necessarily follows from its premises.
Inductive arguments are more complicated, but statistical theory gives us a good handle on exactly what conclusions we may draw from our data. However, given that we’re talking about political philosophy (What should policies aim at, what is the role of government etc), induction is rarely if ever employed. In this blog format, we at best quote the empirical work done by others, we don’t process policy results ourselves.
Abductive arguments or arguments to the best explanation are even more complicated than induction. B explains A iff p(A|B) > p(A) where A is a given and p(A) is the antecedent probability of A. The problem, however, is that what counts as a better explanation is not always so straightforward. Ideally, we would like p(A|B) = 1 and B to be independently likely to be true. However, this often trivially obtains when B=A. For example if A is the observation that the grass is wet, then ay explanation for why the grass is wet would be such that grass would be more likely to be wet if the explanans B obtained than otherwise. For example, raining the previous night would make it more probable that grass was wet. Someone sneaking into our house to water the garden would also make it more probable that the grass was wet. Now, these things could only be explanations if the grass was relatively unlikely to be wet otherwise. However, the latter possibility (the sneaky gardener) is less likely than the former and therefore makes for a worse explanation. Of course, very trivially, the statement that the grass is wet because there is water on it satisfies the formal conditions eve better, but is really just a restatement of the explanandum A. In this context, Stillwater’s comment is apposite:
But at some point the argument’s I make or the views I hold don’t derive from initial premises. They devolve to adhoc-ery. Which isn’t to say that ad hocness is an inconsistency. But when you include too much adhoc-ery, one’s theory gets very close to simply a complete description of preferences. And that’s not a theory anyone could be proud of.
Another deeper problem with abduction when it comes to this kind of normative reasoning is that the explanation so to speak is being used to justify the very “facts” that we used to justify the explanation. i.e. if I am trying to determine whether or not the grass is wet outside, it doesn’t make much sense to try to work backwards and ask what would be the best explanation for the grass being wet. Rather, we could rather look outside and if that is not possible, try to determine if any of the possible causes of wet grass actually obtained. But that is an entirely different kind of thing from trying to find the best explanation for a given phenomenon. We can see how this would go wrong when we fill in more details. There is a whole list of positions out there: i.e. on abortion, trade, regulations, unions, the death penalty, abortion, gay marriage etc.
As Stillwater intimated above, any perceived inconsistency can be trivially resolved by invoking a principle which would distinguish between the situations. However, very quickly, the invoking of such principles becomes extremely ad-hoc such that a complete statement of one’s principles just is a statement of one’s political preferences. The problem with having ad-hoc principles is that there is basically nothing else that justifies such a principle (and the conclusions themselves cannot justify the principles). Then, in that case we have no reason to hold on to said principle and by extension, the conclusions that the principle “explains”. While such a method may give us the most plausible principle that justifies our beliefs about justice and morality, it does not give us any way to adjudicate between different moral beliefs.
Now, of course one possible objection to this criticism of abduction is that our initial moral judgments are good enough to serve at least as a starting point. Principles are chosen in light of these judgments and may if sufficiently well supported by the majority of our strongest judgments, be used to revise some other judgments. In this view, when moral theorizing, a moral/political theory is better if it keeps to most of our common sense judgments even at the cost of some contradictions or ad-hoc features. i.e. here, taking things to their logical conclusion is something we shouldn’t do.
It is in light of the above kinds of objections that the following kinds of comments make sense.
Sonmi says:
I would guess that most people don’t start from first principle reasoning of what an ideology should be and construct their whole views, opinions and belief system based on that. Most people believe certain things about certain issues, and then look for which political ideology or political parties best fit their views on those issues, making compromises along the way
Liberty60 agrees:
I scorned socialists for that very reason- that they let an abstract ideology define their beliefs, and followed it to its conclusion regardless of how absurd the outcome
And in a later post, Tod Kelly agrees:
Take almost any position and if you follow it to an extreme, it’s often best to be able to say “yeah, well not that.” Refusing to budge on any little thing for any little reason in the name of purity of thought is the stuff of dystopias
As do Jason Kuznicki:
I actually agree, mostly. I’m a Hayekian, not a Rothbardian. I don’t do first principles and deduction. I much prefer lived experience and incremental change
And Pierre Corneille
I do think it is possible to be so caught up in consistency that one comes off as an absolutist, uncompromising person. I have a trotskyist friend is who is very consistent in his views (with some exceptions, as I imagine is true of everyone), and he’d be quite a scary dude if his proposed revolution ever really had a chance to take off.
The thing is I don’t think our moral intuitions are worth jack shit. People differ vis-à-vis their intuitions so much on so many issues that they usually contain more heat than light. And it is absolutely mysterious how people expect their gut to have any access to moral truth? Why is it that when your arguments start leading you to “absurd” results it is somehow indicative of something having gone wrong? I hate to sound like an objectivist, but relying on your commonsense judgments is just anti-reason. There is no rational basis for doing so. In order to make any kind of incremental change, we can only know that we are taking a step, however small, in the right direction. However, there is no way to know whether the direction you are going in is the right one without working out in advance what your views are. Even more importantly, in order to take the view that we should be incrementalists rather than radicals, it is not enough to say that radicalism produces certain consequences. Nor is it enough to say that many people think that these consequences are bad. We must be able to show that they are bad, or unjust or that the founding fathers thought it was bad. i.e. when someone comes up to you and says: We find these principles to be self-evident… you don’t just uncritically accept said principles, you ask whether they really are self-evident. Yes I am the guy who will probably respond that I don’t find them self-evident. That people are endowed with certain rights in virtue of being persons may be a true proposition, but it is not self evident. And it is a failure of reason to fail to question whether such pronouncements are in fact true.
None of this is to say that I am immune to error, only that if we do find ourselves facing a contradiction, or holding an ad-hoc principle, we know that we are wrong or fail to adequately justify our beliefs. What this means is that accusations of inconsistency or ad-hocness are serious accusations. A valid argument proceeding from really self-evident premises will contain true conclusionsand be indefeasible in a certain kind of way that cannot be defeated by thought experiments, trolley cases etc. Whatever rightful purchace such tools have on our reason, they cannot be more than the result of a sound deductive argument which is necessarily true.
This brings me to address one last point by Mr Kelly:
Yep. This is pretty much Philosophy in a nutshell. Rewriting reality to make it fit more neatly into your clever world view.
What, liberals aren’t for all those thing? No, no, don’t admit error. Just go back and make your argument longer, and use bigger words. You’ll get there!
The difference I have with Tod is that I think that it is insufficient to take liberalism to be what self-identified liberals believe. There are two reasons. The first is that most people lack consistent beliefs and taking what they believe to be liberalism as liberalism is kind of like using a strawman as I could easily use the nearest consistent version. The second reason is the Americans use the term liberalism idiosyncratically. Liberalism has become a smear word for the entire left. I wouldn’t necessarily characterise Mr Kelly, Stillwater et al as liberals. Rather, they are some kind of moderate egalitarian pragmatist. The care a lot about equality and the common good and they search for policies that best realise their goals of increasing equality and the common good. Now, I am not arguing that this is wrong (but it has to be because I am not an egalitarian pragmatist! *grin*) All I am saying is that the sum total of their political beliefs is better characterised by something else other than liberalism, which has a very specific meaning, and which refers to a group of ideologies with certain central concerns which are themselves somewhat contested. Now, of course I will have to make an argument for that which I am not making here. What it boils down to is this: I will say that ultimately X or Y or Z are fundamental liberal values because embracing them gives us policy positions that cohere with most of what we take to be provisionally liberal views. If we really cared about those values, we would embrace W, which we don’t. Now, my argument for W may ultimately not be successful. For example I suspect that that could be possible about my abortion argument. But because the argument uses concerns that are central to liberalism to make the move it does, whether or not it is successful, it is a liberal argument.
You would also have to contend with people arguing that your argument about Rawls and the veil of ignorance as it applies to the abortion question is flawed, no? So it’s not just the question of people rejecting W even though it fits with fundamental liberal values because of their flawed “moral intuition”, it’s also the question of whether it’s even universally-accepted that W actually does fit with fundamental liberal values. I don’t have a problem with you calling it a liberal argument; I have a problem with you saying that if people believe X, Y and Z, then they must also believe W, otherwise they’re not a consistent liberal, since whether or not W actually follows from fundamental liberal values is a disputed fact. Not sure if I’mmaking myself clear here, W is the abortion position in this case.Report
Sonmi let’s clear 2 things.
1. Let’s say that I find that my argument doesn’t work and is actually begging the question. Then of course I’m not going to say that people who believe X, Y and Z should also believe W.
2. But what if the argument works? What if the logic really is tight? I mean, if the logic is tight, and the argument is a liberal argument then why can I not say that liberals (i.e. people who believe X Y and Z) should also believe W?
Of course all this hangs on whether the logic of the argument obtains. The sense I was getting from the criticism you were making was that even giving an argument of that type was problematic in and of itself regardless of whether the argument ended up being sound or not. But maybe I’m mis-interpreting you.Report
Who gets to define whether the logic is tight? You? General consensus from liberals? The position about abortion taken by Rawls himself?
I don’t have the same disregard you feel for moral intuition, so I would be more inclined to trust that rather than striving for ideological consistency. At the end of the day, an ideology is also created by human, so it’s up to each individual to apply his/her judgment and yes, moral intuition, to the results coming from the ideology as well.Report
Who gets to define whether the logic is tight? You?
Wait, I’m talking about cases where the conclusion follows strictly from the premises. If laid out explicitly everyone should be able to see it. If I am the only one seeing it or not then something has gone wrong. Either I’ve not stated the argument as clearly as I could or the logic isnt tight. The way this could be challenged would be by showing where it broke down.
So, if I said if A then B, then you could deny this by showing me cases of A which did not coincide with B.
Or if I said the following:
1. If A then B
2. B
3. Therefore A.
You would show me that just because 1 and 2 are true doesnt mean that 3 obtains. B could happen without A. i.e. just like in maths, working can be shown and the answers precisely demonstrated.Report
I wouldn’t go quite that far. Our intuitions are in many cases the product of either decades (or centuries) of cultural practice or even millions of years of evolution. This suggests they are at least not sufficiently harmful to destroy society, and may even contribute to a stable and prosperous society.
Naturally they shouldn’t be a stopping point, for one thing our society is quite different to the time in which many of our moral sentiments developed, and there are some aspects of our common sense that were never well anchored to reality in the first place (our common sense developed for dealing with small groups of people, it’s not going to be very good outside that context).
Still I think it’s worthwhile to try and reconcile a moral theory with our intuitions – if they differ we should try to figure out why.Report
Yeah, but a republican’s intuitions are quite different from a democrat’s whose intuitions are yet again different from yours in certain important ways. All of you come fromlong lasting successful societies. Hell, the intuition that slavery is wrong is just 150 years old (maybe 250). Such societies lasted for 1000s of years. Also, it is not clear why we should want a stable and prosperous society. You see what I’m trying to get at here? I’m trying to say that unless we already have a moral theory that tells us that having a prosperous stable society is good or a minimal requirement, we cannot point to the importance of intuitions. But in getting this theory, our use of intuitions would be circular.Report
I do see your point. All I’m saying is that intuitions may inform our attempts at moral theorizing. I don’t consider them a replacement.Report
I see what you’re saying here, but the term ‘moral intuitions’ is ambiguous between a cultural and an intellectual meaning. Personally, I agree with you that culturally determined moral intuitions – the feelings in your gut, say – are generally meaningless wrt informing objective moral issues – tho they are probably very informative wrt prioritizing individual preferences within any culture. But there is another sense of intuition – one which is revealed when you carve off all the cultural and idiosyncratic clothes moral judgments are usually dressed in. I think those intuitions (those are the only thing I refer to as intuitions) are very informative about moral issues.Report
The first quoted comment depends on the concept of direct harm, and references “life and liberty” as the basis of direct harm. It can be shown from the resultant position that the conclusion that any manner of embryo/zygote/fetus is not “life,” and therefore to fish off is the logical conclusion.
But there’s really no justification for the basis of “life.”
I like Nob’s point that to conceive by ordinary mechanical* means entails repeated loss of life.
Thus, the basis must be something other than the barest scrap of life.
I see your point here, and I’ve written a few essays on it before, when the rhetoric of the right applied to finance and finance only, where all other manner of rights were disregarded. Read through the Sharon Statement and see how that rhetoric reflects Geo. W. Bush, and you’ll see what I mean.
On the other hand, the “neo-progressive” movement (as far as I can tell) took off with the Port Huron Statement, which is notable for its opposition to nuclear energy (whereas “green” energy is a big deal to Leftists these days). From there on out, the American Left developed from the student protests of the 60’s into institutions in the 70’s. The institutions became radicalized in the 80’s, and gained more power in the 90’s (squelching opposing views).
For much of the current century, the American Left has been pre-occupied with opposing Bush 43.
But that’s a short synopsis of my own “History of the Left, Part One.”
But, from what I see, that’s where the disjointedness of views stems from; they were, at the very first, a disjointed grouping.
* I use “mechanical” in the sense of physic; ie non-medical. You know, the rhythmic, sweaty stuff.Report
Tagged: http://rustbeltphilosophy.blogspot.com/2012/02/either-be-close-to-truth-or-produce.htmlReport