Whaddaya Mean, “Activist”?
I wanted to give a lawyer’s perspective to the discussion of judicial activism the decision has spawned between William, John, and E.D., arising in part due to Mr. Sullum and Mr. Whelan. To be sure, I think E.D. is wrong to the extent he argues that the Iowa decision is justified because it reaches a rights-enhancing, morally just result; William is exactly right in arguing that the process by which the Court reached its decision is more important than whether the result is just an essential element of whether a decision is “undeniably good.”
Where I get frustrated with cries of “activism,” though, is that they rarely engage the text of the very documents that underly their concern for separation of powers. Certainly “results-oriented” judging is something that is deeply problematic and improperly usurps the role of the legislature, but such judging is far more rare than believed (by critics of both the Right and Left, I might add), and complaints of “results-orientation” usually bespeak a lack of familiarity with the subject at hand.
The most honest definition of activism as a perjorative, and the one advanced by Sullum, John, Daniel Larison in the comments to John’s post, and (I think) William, is that activism is a defiance of the original intent of a Constitution’s drafters, that creates a sort of lawless judiciary that usurps the role of the other branches.
There are a number of problems with this argument, and a focus on “original intent” is far from the exclusive means of putting forth a jurisprudence that relies on a static set of rules for what is and is not within the realm of the judiciary.
The first problem, as Br. Dave so beautifully explained in this must-read post, is that arguments for originalism are typically based on a conception of originalism that really has its roots in the New Deal – and thus is not originalism at all.
The second problem is that “original intent” is a meaningless standard that itself engenders the very sort of judicial activism that it purports to avoid. Constitutions are the result of numerous contributions and compromises from and between individual drafters; the idea that these drafters had any kind of uniform “intent” is, frankly, absurd. All we have to go by are the actual words that they chose to use to express their contributions and compromises.
To be sure, if we are to have any set standards, we may need to look at the definitions of those words as they were understood at the time. But if we stop at those definitions, then we will often wind up with results that are far more libertarian than most originalists, including even some libertarians, are willing to concede. Indeed, sometimes those results can be so libertarian as to be absurd – what if, for instance, Justice Scalia had chosen a strictly textual interpretation of the 2nd Amendment in Heller, resulting in a right to own even a nuclear weapon? What, then, becomes the limiting principle?
To the originalist (including originalists who acknowledge the lack of a definable “original intent”), the limiting principle is whether a particular restriction was common at the time the Constitutional provision entered into law. The presumption here is that if a law was common at the time, then a constitutional provision cannot be deemed to prohibit that practice. But this is ultimately no different from the problems with divining the “intent” of the drafters. It limits the power of their words without any reference to the words themselves, in effect assuming an ambiguity and resolving it in favor of the legislative body where no ambiguity exists.
Sullum is guilty of making this assumption when he writes:
It’s clear that the Iowa constitution’s equal protection clause, at the time it was adopted, was not understood to prohibit a law limiting marriage to a man and a woman (assuming the issue would even have been intelligible).
But the issue probably was NOT intelligible, and even if it was, it was certainly not considered during the drafting of the amendment! Yet originalism assumes that the drafters’ failure to consider the issue means that the language cannot be read to reach that issue. As such, the language is to be read as if it specifically exempted that issue from its reach. This gives drafters entirely too much credit, to say the least, and without justification reads into the provision limiting language the drafters hypothetically would have inserted had they known how the provision would be applied.
A Constitution is only as good as the words it uses, just as a contract is only as good as the words it uses. And just as with any contract, attempts to create ambiguities based on facts that were never incorporated into the document’s language are the truly problematic – and indeed “activist” – endeavors. The far more appropriate role for the judiciary in each instance is to interpret the contract/Constitution only as written, and to insist that, if the parties wish to account for some sort of a changed or unconsidered circumstance, they amend the agreement.
This isn’t to say that a provision such as an equal protection or privileges or immunities clause, or really any other rights-granting provision, is entitled to a boundless interpretation. After all, it is inevitable that such provisions may conflict with each other, and will quite frequently conflict with Constitutionally granted government powers more generally. When that happens, though, the solution isn’t to render one or the other clauses without meaning on that issue; it is instead to analyze whether the stated goal of a policy or law under review may be accomplished in a way that is consistent with both provisions. If it cannot, then it is the role of the courts to ensure that the legitimate government goal is accomplished in a manner that minimizes impact on the other clause(s) of the contract. And that is why things like strict and/or intermediate scrutiny are so utterly essential to Constitutional law, even though they are not explicitly in the document; they provide an avenue or, as Dave argued, a Rule of Construction, by which we can resolve unforeseen conflicts between Constitutional provisions.
Courts cannot be expected to read limiting language into Constitutional provisions to correct for a drafter’s failure to explicitly or implicitly account for issues the drafter may or may not have considered in the first place. To do so would be, well, activism in the very worst sense of the word.
Instead of short-circuiting the political process, decisions such as the Iowa SSM decision are usually best viewed as the Court preventing another branch of government from doing exactly that – no matter how old that short-circuit may be. The proper response to such decisions, by those who disagree with them as a matter of policy, is to go back and correct the short-circuit.
Well put.
There’s also the matter of precedent to consider when discussing judicial activism. What annoys me about this discussion is when the right is when they complain about judges “legislating from the bench.” Um, that’s exactly what they’re supposed to do: in a common law system, we use precedents to apply old rulings to new situations. It’s quicker and more dynamic, though it does give judges an awful lot of power, and I wouldn’t be terribly upset with something like fixed but renewable judicial terms as something of a check on judicial power.
All I ask is that we admit that this isn’t a civil law system (outside of Louisiana) and that it’s not just the Constitution and the laws we pass that determine what the law is. And it’s the right decision, as civil law systems are popular in Europe, and largely unworkable, for some of the reasons Mark explains here: finding the exact intent from a strictly textual reading is complicated and difficult, and everything moves a heck of a lot slower.Report
Lev – very good points that supplement this quite well. A decision that has policy implications that are unpopular can always be overturned by the other branches of government, either through amendment or through corrective legislation, depending on the circumstances. On the other hand, the courts may only overturn a law or policy to the extent it conflicts with established precedent; even when they exceed these bounds (which again is far less often than critics of any nature are willing to admit), the legislature and executive have the ability to overturn those decisions in a way that the courts simply lack the ability to ignore. Superseding statutes and, on the state level at least, constitutional amendments get passed quite often. Given that (and especially given the fact that the judiciary must depend on the executive to enforce its decisions), it is exceedingly difficult to understand how any judicial decision could conceivably “usurp” the power of the legislature in a big-picture sense. Report
William is exactly right in arguing that the process by which the Court reached its decision is more important that whether the result is just.
Oh, the humanity!
Report
Mark and Bob,
That’s not quite what I said. I was pretty careful to say that an “undeniably good” decision requires both proper process and proper outcome, not that process is always and everywhere more important than outcome. I’m open to a scenario where fudging on process is the only way to a just outcome. (District judges in the fifth circuit during the 1960s, perhaps? It’s been a while since I’ve read about this.)
-wrbReport
William – my apologies; I’ll correct that. That said, I personally still take the position that process in the courts is more important than the outcome.
On the rest of the post, I wasn’t sure if you were also making an argument for originalism, which is why I qualified my inclusion of your argument in the body of the post. Let me know if you think that qualified inclusion is unfair.
Report
Qualified inclusion is fair. I find originalism appealing but I’ve got a ways to go before I could say I am justified in believing it. Thanks!Report
This is a hard one for me. I like to think that I favor process over results but it’s not always so simple. There are cases where the legislature avoids hard decisions by forcing them on the courts and cases where the courts abdicate their responsibility by labeling difficult cases “political questions” which result in an establishmentarian regime. Report
Cascadian:
1. Good to hear from you again!
2. I’m hoping to deal with the “political question” and “nonjusticiability” issue in a follow-up post – you’re right that it’s a tough issue. I do think there are times when the “political question” doctrine makes quite a bit of sense, and I’d even argue that in terms of the currently-pending case in California on Prop 8, the political question doctrine may be particularly appropriate.
3. I still owe you a post on the 14th Amendment. I’ve got some research material put together, but I haven’t had time to give it the appropriate attention.Report
Sorry, I haven’t had time to post much lately. Still check in to see what’s up, but haven’t had the time to offer anything…. kids, spring break, relationships…. I’m sure you know how it is. I look forward to your posts but I enjoy most all of what goes on here, even when I disagree. I’m a big fan of this site, I’ve just been busy.Report
Mark:
By the way, have you seen the case (I think it came out of Alaska) where someone actually challenged the 14th and the courts ruled it a political question? Report
I know how it goes, believe me – still, it’s good to have you around.
As for the Alaska case, I hadn’t heard of it until just now. It’s pretty clear that the 9th Circuit didn’t take the Complaint seriously. But to be perfectly honest, I can’t really blame them. Still, something like the validity of a Constitutional ratification is exactly the sort of thing that courts are rightly wary of getting involved with because there really are no judicially manageable standards that can be applied. The authority of the federal courts, with a few irrelevant exceptions, derives exclusively from Article III of the Constitution, and the jurisdiction of those courts is created by Congress. Included in Article III’s grant is the power to decide cases “arising under” the Constitution; but a challenge of the validity of an amendment thereto doesn’t really “arise under” the Constitution – it challenges the validity of part of the very document that grants the courts their authority. There’s a lot more to it, and I’m not sure I can explain it to your satisfaction, but the end result is that ruling on a ratification challenge very much could touch of a Constitutional crisis by usurping authority that is quite specifically delegated to Congress. Report
Dang, lost a post. I would think that the court would rightfully have jurisdiction and rule on the proceedural issues around the enactment of the fourteenth. On the other side, I would think that Marbury would be an example of what your talking about, but that’s more or less accepted law, give or take a few signing statements. Report