Impulses and Vectors
Responding to my defense of the value of libertarianism/blatant excuse to repost Mr. Henley’s Jester quote, OG regulars Michael Drew and Bob make some great points about the idea of libertarianism-as-vector that led me to some unexplored thoughts about ideological frameworks.
First, Michael wonders whether the concept of libertarianism-as-vector means that libertarianism can be a component of any and all lines of political thought, and asking “what is it that distinguishes a libertarian qua person from someone who merely allows the libertarian vector a healthy role within her thought” if libertarianism is merely a vector? Then Bob goes on to note that the libertarianism-as-vector concept that I stole from Jaybird (who stole it from an unknown source) appears to originate from an article that labels all political ideology as vector. The implication, then, is presumably that these vectors are presumably at work within all of us at a given time. I don’t know if Bob also intended to suggest this, but I think this also implies that political labels are truly meaningless for any purpose other than stating which vector a person believes carries the strongest priority at a given moment in time.
I think both Michael and Bob are basically right, here, particularly in suggesting that all ideologies are just impulse or vectors that reside in varying degrees within us all. If this is true, then, why would it be important that there be a group of people who self-identify as libertarians in our national debates?
The answer to this is, I think, non-obvious. But what it comes down to is this: depending on the core political philosophy with which we most readily identify, we are going to be more likely to ignore, more or less completely, our impulses that would ordinarily lead us in the opposite direction. It’s a confirmation bias problem that can be solved only by listening to people whose philosophical underpinnings lead them to predominantly favor other vectors.
What’s important to recognize here is that we all have philosophical underpinnings for our vectors that lead us to self-identify as libertarian, conservative, liberal, etc. I think this is true whether or not we’ve actually read Hayek, Burke, Rawls, or Marx. However, no philosophically pure state of any sort has ever existed as a stable society (maybe I’m wrong about this). There’s never been a stable anarchic society in recorded history, nor has there ever been a stable large-scale society that has managed to completely block dynamism, nor has there ever been a purely egalitarian society. Yet the lack of such societies does not invalidate any of these philosophical underpinnings, which are at root normative beliefs about the ultimate “good” that are simply unfalsifiable.
Let me illustrate (keeping in mind that this illustration will necessarily be overly-generalized):
Conservative philosophical underpinnings view dynamism as a threat to tradition and social order; a conservative will thus be relatively unconcerned with undertaking social change to solve problems, but will be quite concerned with deterring threats (whether external or internal) to established order. As such, the conservative impulse to dealing with problem X will be to either question whether problem X exists or to question whether it is a severe enough problem to warrant solving. Indeed, if the conservative believes that problem X does not, in fact, exist, he will perhaps actively work for legal changes that would prevent a solution to problem X (see, e.g., anti-gay marriage legislation), as that solution itself may be a threat to tradition and social order. If something is viewed as a threat to established social order, then that threat must be defeated. The internal contradiction here, of course, is that s0metimes government action to prevent social change can itself be a social change, which is, I think, why paleo-conservatives so often seem to sound identical to libertarians. This is not to say that conservatives are incapable of acknowledging the existence of a problem, just that the burden of proof is going to be abnormally high, and the preferred solution is going to be particularly focused, with little concern as to the direction of that solution (ie, more government/less government). Moreover, in some ways, conservatives may be abnormally far-sighted in that their concerns about threats to order and tradition ensure that they are abnormally vigilant about some future problems that don’t yet exist (see, e.g., conservative worries about the long-term cultural effects of illegal immigration).
The liberal’s philosophical underpinnings, however, will be more quick to acknowledge the existence and severity of a given ongoing problem. For liberals, the response to the problem, once acknowledged, is generally going to be to look for ways that society can fix the problem – and of course, government is the tool through which society attempts to fix problems, particularly collective action problems. So for liberals, the initial impulse once a problem is acknowledged is going to be that government is capable of solving the problem and that the problem is a result of private behavior (which is almost always true in the sense that the most immediate cause of most collective action problems is the acts of private individuals).
The self-identified libertarian will also be relatively quick to acknowledge the existence of a problem, perhaps due to the common roots of liberalism and libertarianism. To be sure, he may often acknowledge a somewhat different set of problems than the liberal, but broadly speaking, the libertarian is philosophically just as willing to enable widespread social change as the liberal.
Where libertarians diverge from liberals is that their philosophical skepticism about the capability of government ensures that their first reaction to a problem is to ask what government is doing to create that problem in the first place.
The thing is, once the conservative, liberal, or libertarian has gone down a path that separates from the status quo-preserving position of “do nothing” (whether to respond to a future threat or an immediate problem), it is extremely easy to forget your lesser impulses. Confirmation biases immediately come into play, and they are made worse by the fact that modernity is so complex that it is rarely possible to prove to an absolute certainty that problem/threat X is caused by Condition Y or will be solved by Action Z. There will usually be at least some empirical evidence supporting each position: do nothing, do more, or do less. We will look at the evidence that supports the path we have already chosen, and ignore the evidence that doesn’t.
And that’s where having opponents with a philosophically-grounded theory of government is so important. They force us to ask the question of whether our preferred response to problem X excessively undermines our lower-priority, but still important, impulses in favor of conservatism, libertarianism, or modern liberalism. They challenge whether the empirical justifications for our preferred response can be explained by our philosophical justifications. Most importantly, perhaps, they force us to consider whether there is a way of responding to problem X that is consistent with more than one (and maybe all) of those normative impulses that we all share in one degree or another.
It is at all times necessary to have each of these predominant worldviews in our national dialogue (rather than merely existing as understood but untapped impulses within each of us) if we wish democracy to be successful. The conservative worldview, by itself, can act only as a brake on the excesses of liberalism or libertarianism – it is incapable of reversing those excesses. Liberalism and libertarianism, meanwhile, would descend society into anarchy if they existed without some group that was motivated primarily by traditionalism and preservation of order – it would be difficult to to rely on the rule of law if that law was in a constant state of flux, ping-ponging between existing and not existing.
Of course, if there were no group calling itself libertarian, liberal, or conservative, those values would not just disappear since most of us possess them to some degree or another. However, having opponents who self-identify with or at least consciously adhere to something resembling those worldviews reminds us that we do, in fact, care about the values underlying that opposition. We then have to make the conscious decision not to care in that particular instance.
Very good. My only disagreement is with liberalism as an agent of dynamic change as opposed to conservatism’s attempt to maintain tradition. I believe that modern liberal/progressive policies affecting societal problems have been around long enough, since the beginning of the 20th century, to count as tradition. I see conservatives and modern liberals both protecting a two party system which maintains a tension that has become the status quo, leaning toward statism for the most part, and which blocks dynamism that would come from a private sector less burdened by central planning — the whole two-party system can be seen as conservative as compared to the dynamism constrained in the private sector — I don’t necessarily associate the private sphere with libertarianism, but the libertarian impulse is to free the dynamic power of the private sphere.Report
“I believe that modern liberal/progressive policies affecting societal problems have been around long enough, since the beginning of the 20th century, to count as tradition.”
I totally agree with this, which is why you don’t really see much conservative heart to overturn the New Deal. Conservatives will occasionally rail against it, but when push comes to shove, they have zero interest in revisiting it.
I do, however, think liberalism aspires to dynamism as a general goal. Liberals are very much concerned with fixing what they view as problems and generally creating a “better” society, much as libertarians are (or at least ought to be). But generally speaking, their response to the existence of a problem will begin by moving in the opposite direction from libertarianism.
So where a libertarian may look at a given problem and blame FDR, a liberal may look at that same exact problem and argue that the problem is caused by the private sector (which, frankly, is usually correct from the standpoint of determining the most proximate cause, although the libertarian would respond that the proximate cause was itself made inevitable by a government action). The result is that the liberal will look for new government solutions to the problem.
With a liberal worldview, you will often come to the conclusion that government can be a powerful force for change (ie, dynamism). With a libertarian worldview, you will often come to the conclusion that government is a powerful force standing in the way of change.Report
Good essay. I think there is a difference between parties as institutions which seek to survive and beliefs/vectors. So the R and D parties are somewhat separate from the beliefs their members hold. Each party seeks to survive and thrive as a entity. They wouldn’t be much of a party if they didn’t have a desire to keep surviving.
Things get interesting when trying to turn these vectors into concrete policies to govern a country. Most people while generally falling into one of these three general belief systems usually have a strong sympathy towards another one of the beliefs.Report
Thanks. This sounds exactly right.Report
This is one place that I think liberals’ acknowledgement of the power of the market gets short shrift. Modern American liberals are not socialists or communists. I know that trips a lot of current media buzzers in one sentence, but there is a reason those buzzers have come about. Liberals really do value the power of the market, it’s just that they tend to think that its benefits tend to remain powerful even within the constraints of parameters that are set by overriding societal priorities — ones, crucially, that are determined by democratic processes. That is why liberals get touchy about being called socialist (which is in turn why they continue to be called socialists). Of course, what a libertarian sees in the liberal willingness to constrain and define markets by social criteria are primarily the distortions that they believe result from those limits, as well as whatever perverse (perhaps even ironic) social consequences result in turn from those. Libertarians (in whatever political guise) emphasize those distortions and advocate for less intervention (though, significantly, rarely in practice for absolute non-intervention), and thus the comparison in the public mind becomes one of liberals advocating greater control of markets versus libertarians (perhaps not self-identified ones, but nevertheless advancing the market thesis) advocating for less.
What becomes lost in the discussion is how greatly most liberal proposals to address what they see as social failures of the marketplace continue to rely on markets as fundamental mechanisms for allocating resources. If there was one (what I believe to be) misconception of liberals among libertarians that I would most like to dispel, it would be the notion that liberal thought (as opposed to some self-described liberals) in any way rejects the power of the market to efficiently allocate resources, and that in so doing it produces a socially valuable result. In fact, the liberal critique of markets is quite the opposite than that they generally serve no useful social function (or a negative one, for that matter), but rather that, while broadly concurring with the thesis of the superiority of the market economy and embracing it as a fundamentally just way to order economic life, in fact markets often perform excessively efficiently, with outcomes at the extremes that have unacceptable social consequences which cannot justly be allowed to stand.
This then raises what is in my view the most important difference between liberals and libertarians, one that is worth clarifying and emphasizing. That is, each philosophy’s respective view on the question of whether markets continue to operate efficiently, or how efficiently they continue to operate, under constraints placed on them for reasons of social priority, and how much of the social utility of that more-or-less efficient continued operation of markets is preserved under those conditions. To me, that is the salient question that most distinguishes the two, at least in terms of the respective instrumental cases for libertarianism versus liberalism. (There is, of course, always the first-order, non-instrumental, “Don’t tread on me” case for libertarianism, which in my view cannot be dismissed, even while it also does not trump all other social values. To further clarify, in case I am not coming through as I hope, you can think of the instrumental case for libertarianism as epitomized by the arguments of Hayek [whom I have not read], and the non-intrumental case as by Nozick [whom I have sporadically read]. As a [somewhat loosely-committed and, candidly, unfortunately-not-very-well-philosophically-grounded] liberal, the main role that the non-instrumental case plays in my thinking is that it can be used to resolve close questions that remain after the ‘heavy artillery’ of instrumentalist libertarian arguments versus those of social outcome priorities determine the broad order of battle on a question.)
So in my perhaps idiosyncratic view, then, a modern America liberal in many cases is just a moderate libertarian who simply isn’t willing to accept all the consequences of a rigorous libertarian policy program. Scratch many a liberal, and you will find a person who recognizes and sympathizes with many of the more powerful arguments driving libertarianism as a vector, but who doesn’t believe that a full adoption of those principles into policy will have acceptable outcomes, and notes that most libertarians, regardless of self-identification as such, nevertheless do not adopt the hard-line stance, which provides significant justification in the liberal’s mind for the more moderate, pragmatic balancing approach.*
* I should note that one central libertarian argument that really isn’t much acknowledged by liberals is the notion that the ill market effects in need of correction that they identify are in fact the result of status-quo market interventions. That really is one too many wrinkles for most liberals (many of whom view it as a quite-too-convenient holding, while of course libertarians would maintain that it is central to their critique, to which liberals would respond, “Well, exactly,” and round and round), and it is likely an important distinction I am neglecting here.Report
Mark, two quick points.
1. I doubt that Jaybird appropriated the vector term from the site I linked this morning. In other words, I don’t think the term as Jaybird used it was originally found there. Perhaps Jaybird will confirm or reject it as his source.
2. For better or worse I am a labeling kind of guy. But as you point out, lables are just starting points.
Otherwise, very edifying.Report
Doing some quick research, I want to say that I probably stole that quote from Jerry Pournelle.Report
As soon as I thought about it a second I realized “any and all political thought” was probably overstating it a bit on my part — fascist and totalitarian thought are certainly exceptions. Or if they have the vector, it’s with a negative sign in front.Report
Mark, this is excellent stuff and your interlocutors are top shelf. Perhaps, in the future one of the League might take on a further differentiation: something along the lines of …the reality of order in man and society (city), e.g. the order of man’s existence in society. I am interested in what this generation thinks of these things.Report