Intellectual Property, Abstract v. Natural Right, Part II
This is the second post in a series. The first post is here.
In this post, I’m going to get into the weeds of Hegel’s “Elements of the Philosophy of Right”, the Cambridge Text edition. Hegel writes in non-bivalent logic that requires some brain-twisting to decipher for people who haven’t studied differing logics, so if you’re confused about my inability to make strong declarations in this part of the series, bear with me. There are a lot of quotations from the source material.
Abstract Right
Before moving into Section I: Property, it is important to note from §36 of Abstract Right: “The commandment of right is therefore: be a person and respect others as persons”, which is linked to this passage from the Encyclopedia: “It is a duty to possess things as property, i.e., to be as a person; which, in the relation of appearance, positing the reference to another person, develops itself into the duty of the other to respect my right (Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind § 486R).
Property, the possession thereof, and the recognition of property rights are central to Hegel. The reasons for this are clarified below.
Section I: Property
Hegel’s discussion of property is focused into four main sections: the definition of property, the acquisition of property (the act of possessing), the use of property, and the dissolution of ownership (the alienation of property), either by abandonment or transfer to the will of another. We’ll cover the first three parts today. Although Hegel mentions intellectual property specifically early in the chapter, a thorough understanding of property independent of the specific case is necessary for the full understanding of the Hegelian model for property and ownership, so those of you who have read Hegel and are wondering why I’m skipping that section at the moment, don’t worry, we’ll get back to it farther down in this post.
Definition of Property
Property, in the sense of things that can be possessed, consists of things, which Hegel defines in §42 as an external something unfree, impersonal, and without rights. It is useful to look at the examples of things as given in the section. Animals are the first example of what can be considered things. They can intuit, but not with itself as the subject; they possess no capability to examine themselves in the abstract. He continues discussing animals in §44 and §47, to clarify the position of animals as things. The externality of things is an important characteristic, as we will see later.
Taking Possession
Hegel defines taking possession in §54, noting that it consists of three main parts. These are: physical seizure of something, giving it form, and designating its ownership.
Real property (land) is mentioned first in §55. It seems to the modern mind that there is a difference between land ownership and object ownership. Objects, even ones so great as monuments, can be moved from one location to another, but land ownership can only be transferred from one owner to another, not one place to another, as the land is in itself a place. Hegel’s definition of things as external to the will, however, is clearly inclusive of land as a thing. As long as the will can imagine itself as the owner of a thing, the will can possess the thing; physical possession is actually a lesser form of possession. Taking possession by designation (marking something as yours), as Hegel says in §58, “is the most complete mode of all, for the effect of the sign is more or less implicit in the other ways of taking possession, too. If I seize a thing or give form to it, the ultimate significance is likewise a sign, a sign given to others in order to exclude them and to show that I have placed my will in the thing.”
Use of the Thing
It is clear in §59 that it is the act of possession is not enough to constitute property, as “Use is the realization of my need through the alteration, destruction, or consumption of the thing, whose selfless nature is thereby revealed and which thus fulfills its destiny… When I and the thing come together, one of the two must lose its distinct quality in order that we may become identical. But I am alive, a willing and truly affirmative agent; the thing, on the other hand, is a natural entity.” Indeed, Hegel goes further, in §61, “Thus, if I have the whole use of the thing, I am its owner; and beyond the whole extent of its use, nothing remains of the thing which could be the property of someone else.” In §62, Hegel further clarifies the concept of ownership by noting that entitlement to partial or temporary use of something is distinguished from ownership, and mentions the particular case of usufruct – the right to use and enjoy another’s property provided that its substance is conserved. Finally, in §63, he provides one additional note regarding ownership: to own a thing is to own both its value and its use; “A family which cannot sell or mortgage its estate is not the proprietor of its value… But since this form of property is out of keeping with the concept of property, such limitations (e.g., feudal tenancies and entails) are now for the most part disappearing.”
Now that we have a brief overview of property in general, we return to §43 of Property, as it is devoted entirely to the subject of accomplishments of the mind: sciences, arts, inventions, and even religious observance. Hegel says of these, “[as] objects of contract; in the way in which they are bought and sold, etc., they are treated as equivalent to things,” (BSK will relate) “… we hesitate to call such accomplishments, knowledge… etc., things; for on the one hand, such possessions are the object of commercial negotiations and agreements, yet on the other they are of an inward and spiritual nature.” He further recognizes that, “possession of body and spirit which is acquired through education, study, habituation, etc., and which constitutes an inner property of the spirit will not be dealt with here. But the transition of such intellectual property into externality, in which it falls within the definition of legal and rightful property, will be discussed only when we come to the disposal of property.”
Hegel acknowledges here that intellectual property is unlike other (external) things in that the acquisition and dissolution of intellectual property on the first hand alters the property of the spirit acquiring the property, and thus the disposal of this class of property will be unlike that of other property, as that which has become part of the spirit cannot be relinquished. He obviously has some struggles dealing with this (indeed, I’d argue that he basically kicks the can down the road because he can’t resolve it to his own satisfaction).
A summary translation into the vernacular, so far: if you build me a waterwheel, and I use the waterwheel to make flour, pretty much everything involved is entirely external. The value of the flour is measurable. However, if you show me a movie, the value of that movie *to me* is primarily a function of its ability to impact the spirit, according to Hegel. Thus, my assessment of the value of the movie is uniquely individual to me, and it would thus be difficult for the artist to properly price such a thing. For those people who make lists of “books that changed my life” or “movies that I would take to a desert island”, this concept is not entirely alien. Moreover, if I myself am a practitioner of the same work of the mind that you are, I am – by exposure to your instance of the craft – necessarily altered internally by your work. An author who reads Shakespeare is necessarily changed in his or her own ability to write literature. But this changing is internal to the author, and thus again cannot necessarily be meaningfully measured.
Further, from the previously discussed paragraphs, Hegel’s hesitation is readily explicable from the ontological problems inherent in viewing these accomplishments of the mind as property by his definition. In order to be an owner of a thing, one must possess the whole of the thing, so that nothing remains of the thing which could be the property of someone else; this presents obvious difficulties for the transfer of ownership of accomplishments of the mind. He works some of this out in the section on Contract, which we will cover in Part III.
Moreover, the act of the use of the thing is itself subject to problems of definition for each certain type of accomplishments of the mind. The meaning of “use” for physical objects is fairly clear when expressed in the will, even to any other independent will which can observe the owner and describe the use of the thing objectively. The use of lyrical poetry or philosophy or music or literature is not quite as clear, particularly to the observer who is not the owner. It can be generally said that the use of certain sorts of accomplishments of the mind, particularly the arts, is very nearly only the act of altering the property of the spirit which is using the property. Since this use is entirely internal to the will, it will defy ready or entire explanation to anyone other than that will that takes possession of it. The use of inventions is more like that of physical things, but is still different, as Hegel will discuss later in the section on Alienation of Property.
Finally, an important note for today’s reader is that entailed property is explicitly considered by Hegel “out of keeping with the concept of property”, and yet it seems clear that intellectual property is entailed in the sense of its value and its use, in practice. Hold onto that note.
As mentioned earlier, the scale and scope of the difference between patent and copyright law suggests qualitative differences between the two, and yet Hegel describes them without differentiation except in general terms. As the product of a pre-Industrial and pre-Informational age, the implications of use and ownership of this property, and thus their value, were in relative infancy. This is open to assessment at the end of the series.
I await further entries in this series, but based on this it seems that conceiving of copyright, etc, as intellectual “property” is perhaps flawed.Report
Spoiler alert: see rot13.com to decypher:
Arvgure Urtry abe Ybpxr ernyyl unf n tbbq sbhaqngvba sbe vagryyrpghny cebcregl nf rvgure na nofgenpg evtug (Urtry) abe angheny evtug (Ybpxr). Ubjrire, lbh pna znxr pregnvayl gur pnfr gung gurve erfcrpgvir senzrjbexf obgu nyybj sbe fbzr vapneangvba bs gur vqrn, jvgu abgnoyr ahnaprf.
Urtry, va cnegvphyne, jbhyq unir fbzr frevbhf vffhrf jvgu gur jnl jr punenpgrevmr vagryyrpghny cebcregl. N ohapu bs gur guvatf gung gur ynj pheeragyl rapbqrf nf npprcgnoyr hfrf bs VC haqre pbagenpg Urtry jbhyq syngyl ershfr gb fhccbeg nf gur rffragvny rdhvinyrag bs fynirel.Report
Haqre pbagenpg? Ubj fb? N pbagenpg vf na nterrq na rkpunatr bs pbafvqrengvba; V cnl lbh zbarl, lbh trg gb hfr gur cebqhpgf bs zl zvaq. Guvf vf abg fynirel.Report
Lbh’yy frr jura jr trg gurer.Report
In considering land as property, did Hegel give consideration to alloidial estates? (This is playful, not serious; allodial estates are not really much in play anymore.)
More seriously, I can see the beginning of the idea versus expression concept so critical to copyright in Hegel’s distinguishing between the “inner property of the mind” and the “external product of the mind” which can be bought and sold.Report
Student Likko has precognition. Tomorrow, I should have the next post up. The abdication of property, and contract.Report
Oh, on the alloidial estates: not specifically. This is what he’s talking about (more or less) when he’s talking about entailed estates – sort of – in the sense that inheritance of the landed gentry wasn’t “true” ownership in the Hegelian sense, since typically all those lands came loaded with legal constraints on selling them or whatnot.
I think the German/Prussian landed gentry history is probably sufficiently different from the English aristocracy that alloidial estates as a specific form weren’t mentioned.
Of course, I had to look up “alloidial estates”, so I’m guessing based upon what I read in the last 30 minutes 🙂Report
The concept of Property seems more properly addressed in law, not philosophy. I did some work for an IP lawyer in Arizona some while back who explained just how arbitrary some of these concepts become, especially in the realm of patents.Report
Sure; in fact, further spoiler alert, a goodly portion of our legal concept of intellectual property law has grounding in either Hegel or Locke (IMO) although neither of them is the clear-cut progenitor and the parts that wound up in the legal code are (again, IMO) more an artifact of “those things that could be manipulated at the time for advantage of vested interests”, but that’s a whole ‘nuther party of posts.Report
It took me a full day to get my head wrapped around the notion of Indefeasibility. So much of the concept of Property revolves around what it Isn’t, not what it is.Report
My problem, or more properly, my confused ratiocination on the subject, comes down to three different and troublesome definitions of Property, all of which afflict me in some form or other.
Accounting has its own definitions for Assets and Capital Items. Taxation demands to know who owns what. Software, well, I let my lawyer and my clients work out what’s theirs, but I don’t think I’ve ever had a truly original idea for all the supposedly “original” work I’ve done. It’s all been in the math and logic textbooks, or in Knuth. The notion of patenting software just amuses me. The world would be a hugely better place if GNU licenses applied everywhere. There’s enough work to be done in the world without encumbering software with all this nonsensical legalese written by people who couldn’t code up Hello World in any language.Report
I, too, am looking forward to what you think of abandonment or alienation of property, particular with respect to non-physical property. I favor strong property rights, but I also think that many of the laws that attach to physical property–taxation on the value and adverse possession in particular–should be applied as well.Report
I think that Hegel is falling victim to the same “if I can’t pick it up then it isn’t real” fallacy used by so many people discussing intellectual property issues. I think that he’s heading in the right direction when he writes of “accomplishments of the mind” as being “objects of contract” (paraphrasing from Cahalan’s post), because I believe that this is the actual “property” that’s involved in intellectual property. That is, what’s being protected is not the thing itself, but rather the ability to create contracts with that thing as the focus. Indeed, the very term “copyright” tells us what it’s protecting.
Unfortunately, Hegel then wanders off into the weeds of “how can you determine the value of an idea”, which is bunk, because all value is subjective. Even the value of a physical object is subjective; I might not care about a pile of gravel on my yard–in fact, I’d pay to have it hauled away, so it’s of negative value to me–but you might see useful material for aggregate to underlay a foundation, or maybe you see a drainable substrate for a garden, or maybe the gravel is high in bauxite and you happen to own an aluminum foundry. Defining property by the existence of value doesn’t work.
Or, to bring together the informational and the physical, let’s talk about passage rights. Nobody would deny that I have the right to restrict passage over my land–but why do I have that right? Let’s hypothesize that Invisible Joe wants to cut across my yard as a shortcut to his destination, and he can do so without causing any damage or change to the yard, and (as he’s invisible) I wouldn’t even know he was doing it. Do I still have the right to prevent him crossing my yard? Hegel would probably say “yes, Invisible Joe realizes a benefit through interacting with your property, and this constitutes ‘use’, and as you are the acknowledged owner of the property you therefore have the right to control its use.” But doesn’t this provide equal justification for copyright? The person who obtained the intellectual property and allowed it to alter them certainly ‘used’ it; indeed, they might well have used it more fundamentally than Invisible Joe crossing my yard.Report
I don’t think Hegel falls into the “if I can’t pick it up it’s not real” trap. His nuance is “if you can’t give it up, it’s not exactly the same as something you *can* give up”. I can give up a lump of gold, or even give up my claim to land, and give it *to* you. I can’t exactly do the same thing with an invention of mine, because although I can give you the invention, and the plans, and even a promise not to make *that particular* invention, I can’t remove all of the principles of engineering that are embedded in my head that made it possible for me to invent the thing, nor can I prevent myself from using that knowledge again. “How irreducible can such a product be?” is an important nuance to Hegel.
Hegel is transactional, he’s not a natural law guy at all. It’s not a matter of whether or not you have a natural right to property (we’ll get to that in Locke), it’s a matter of how two individuals (or, to a greater extent, an individual and civil society) can interact.Report
” I can give up a lump of gold, or even give up my claim to land, and give it *to* you. I can’t exactly do the same thing with an invention of mine…”
But you can give up your claim to the reproducibility of that invention. And that’s what intellectual property is actually about. People are correct when they say that me copying a song doesn’t deprive the copyright holder of the song, but possession of the song is the result of the infringement, rather than the infringement itself.
” I can’t remove all of the principles of engineering that are embedded in my head that made it possible for me to invent the thing, nor can I prevent myself from using that knowledge again.”
Well…not using knowledge even though you possess it is the essence of the law, isn’t it? I might know that I can smash a shopowner’s window with a brick, but we all agree that it’s against the law to do that.Report
“[T]he scale and scope of the difference between patent and copyright law suggests qualitative differences between the two, and yet Hegel describes them without differentiation except in general terms.”
You say “and yet”, implying that you think Hegel is wrong. I agree with Hegel that an entity of information is, philosophically, the same no matter what shape it is. A patent, a copyright, and a contract–and the deed to a particular piece of land, for that matter–all derive their authority from the same philosophical basis.Report
That is not my implication (although I can see how you read it that way). I’m just pointing out that there is a discrepancy between the Hegelian framework and the existing framework of intellectual property law.
I’ll get to my idea after I get through Hegel and Locke. Right now these posts are to provide descriptive background.Report