The Promise of Dubious Prisoner Claims of Religious Freedom: An Opportunity for Real Prison Reform
I read Brother Likko’s post on the (often seemingly bizarre) flexibility and questionable sincerity of prisoners’ religious beliefs, and their willingness to file suits to protect those questionable beliefs with great interest. These suits, which are indeed frequently frivolous on their face, are something that Brother Likko indicates he feels compelled to apologize for on behalf of lawyers everywhere (even though most such suits are pro se), as they gum up the system and cost taxpayers money, and I certainly understand where he’s coming from in making such an apology.* However, many of these suits, frivolous as they may be, are likely symptoms of a deep-seated problem with the philosophy that undergirds our prison system. Where Brother Likko anticipates an avalanche of these suits to pick up steam in coming years and hopes that this will ultimately lead to the weakening of exemptions for religious beliefs, I hope and indeed half anticipate that they may finally force the reevaluation of our dehumanizing prison system.
I. The Forthcoming Avalanche of Prisoner Religious Freedom Cases
[N/B: If you’re not interested in a recap of Burt’s post and our longrunning debate on the effect of the Hobby Lobby decision, please feel free to skip to section II]
Burt writes that he believes in the wake of the Hobby Lobby and Holt religious freedom cases**:
A prisoner who claims a religious belief requiring a particular kind of practice could reasonably expect minimal scrutiny of the belief and the practice and whatever kind of prison rule is implicated, and instead enjoy the spectacle of the courts requiring the state’s attorneys to offer elaborate and credibility-straining justifications before eventually losing and having to make special accommodations. It might start with a beard, but there seems to be no limit to where the prisoner-making-the-warden-dance charade might end.
Brother Likko has long expressed concern (particularly as an atheist who fears he is not protected by religious freedom protections) that an expansive reading of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act (“RFRA”) and its near-identical related statute, the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act (“RLUIPA”), will effectively exempt anyone claiming to hold even fairly ridiculous religious beliefs from laws of general applicability. He has also consistently insisted that such an expansive reading of these statutes, demonstrated by Hobby Lobby and Holt, is relatively new and a significant change in the law that may have disastrous consequences. In his current post on prisoner religious freedom litigation, he notes that the religious beliefs of prisoners often appear to be highly plastic and that Hobby Lobby and Holt are thus likely to create a surge in potentially successful (or at least expensive) prisoner religious freedom litigation based on highly dubious “beliefs” of doubtful sincerity. He suggests, finally, that such an increase may create a backlash that, he hopes, will force a weakening of RFRA and RLUIPA.
I must respectfully disagree, which is perhaps not surprising given our debate over the Hobby Lobby case last year. First, I strongly disagree that recent cases have really changed the way that the courts review religious freedom cases. However, it is impossible for me to deny that these cases have been far more high-profile, thus allowing the lowness of the bar for RLUIPA and RFRA claims to be more in the public eye. As such, I suspect Brother Likko is correct that prisoners’ rights litigation under RLUIPA is likely to become even more pervasive in light of these cases, and that claims of sincerity of beliefs are likely to become increasingly questionable. This is true whether or not courts in fact have become/are becoming more receptive to religious freedom claims – as long as there is a mere perception that this is occurring (and I concede that there is), more claims will be filed, which in turn means more claims will be successful and/or will reach a sufficiently high profile to enter the realm of public awareness, even when the sincerity of the belief in question is dubious at best.
II. Why RFRA and RLUIPA Will Not Be Weakened
Unlike Burt, however, I do not think it a given that an increase in successful-but-dubious prisoner religious freedom litigation will create a chance for an “eventual brake on [what Brother Likko views as the] seemingly limitless judicial deference to religious rights.” Instead, I think the trend may create an opening for something few would expect: meaningful prison reform, and perhaps a dramatic shift in the philosophy underlying much of our prison system.
Politically, even with a rise in dubious religious freedom prisoner litigation, I do not think weakening RLUIPA, much less RFRA itself, will be remotely feasible any time soon. These two statutes are broadly – and identically – worded, allowing exemptions for “any exercise of religion, whether or not compelled by, or central to, a system of religious belief,” unless the government can show that applying the rule/law to the plaintiff is both in furtherance of a compelling governmental interest and is the least restrictive means of furthering that interest. The broad reading of which Brother Likko complains is almost impossible to avoid (which is why I disagree that Hobby Lobby and Holt meaningfully expanded these statutes), and thus the only way to narrow either statute would be to do so legislatively on the federal level, which means getting 60 votes in the Senate.
To say that maintaining an expansive version of RFRA (or even creating an even more expansive version) is a high priority issue for evangelical voters, who make up fully half of GOP primary voters, would be an understatement, to say the least. Similarly, it is unimaginable that the small but growing segment of libertarian-ish Republicans would be willing to support legislation that would weaken RFRA. Additionally, a strong RFRA is likely critical to the GOP establishment-types, as it provides a way to maintain peace between social conservatives and more socially moderate or liberal factions that the establishment hopes to attract to the party, as well as potential GOP voters who are not Christian. Although Democrats, post-Hobby Lobby, have almost entirely abandoned the expansive view of religious freedom once most prominently pushed by Justice Brennan, they would be unable to directly weaken RFRA absent a supermajority in the Senate plus control of the House and Presidency.
But Brother Likko’s suggestion seems to imply that RLUIPA, with its protections specifically for prisoners, would be the avenue to chip away at this – while the statutes are near-identical, there is no theoretical reason why RLUIPA couldn’t be weakened as a precursor to weakening RFRA. This, however, is unlikely for two reasons. First, a direct attack on RLUIPA would raise no less vociferous objections from evangelical/religious conservatives – again, the language in RLUIPA and RFRA is identical, so religious conservatives would surely see any proposed attack on RLUIPA as the Trojan Horse that it would, in fact, be. While such a slippery slope concern is less powerful than a direct attack on RFRA might be, there is another – hugely important, but vastly underreported – trend amongst religious conservatives that is specifically relevant to RLUIPA and prisoners’ litigation. Specifically, although religious conservatives are still quite happy to frequently push the law-and-order line, this attitude has reversed dramatically on the topic of prison reform in recent years. Instead, prison reform – a question of Christian mercy – has become an increasingly important issue to evangelical and religious conservatives in recent years, and it is evangelicals who have become arguably the most influential advocates of prisoners’ rights in that period of time. An attack on RLUIPA thus would not only be viewed as a step towards weakening RFRA, it would also be a direct attack on evangelicals’ efforts at prison reform. Meanwhile, an attack on RLUIPA would likely run into opposition from some traditionally liberal groups, not least of which would be the trial lawyers’ association, but also presumably African-American church groups and the ACLU. Whatever support gained for weakening RLUIPA from centrist Republicans would almost certainly be offset y the loss of support from such traditionally Progressive constituencies.
This does not mean, however, that nothing will happen as a result of a hypothetical increase in dubious prisoner litigation. To the contrary – and counterintuitively, given the dubious nature of such suits – such a hypothetical increase in prisoner litigation may cause us to dramatically rethink the way our prison systems operate in this country.
III. Why a Rise in Dubious RLUIPA Claims May Force Meaningful Reform of Our Prisons
To be clear, an explosion in successful (or even just unsuccessful but expensive) RLUIPA suits would create a potentially huge problem that could not simply be ignored. It would increase the strain on already overburdened courts, and increase the cost of our prison system, amongst other problems no doubt. The cheapest and easiest way to solve such a problem would be, as Brother Likko suggests, weakening RLUIPA, but as I mention above, this would probably not be politically feasible.
The more workable way of preventing RLUIPA suits, then, may be to change the philosophy of how prisons are run in this country such that they reevaluate the purpose of prison and, in the process, are able to more unquestionably comply with RLUIPA. Such reforms would not require much in the way of legislation, as most policies are typically questions of administrative rules or even just individual warden decision-making, meaning that these types of reforms could often be implemented through focused lobbying campaigns rather than time-consuming and politically difficult coalition building and compromising. National legislation in particular would be unnecessary given that federal prisoners are only a small fraction of those serving time in American prisons.
And let me be clear: a dramatic rise in successful or at least costly RLUIPA suits could only be solved by a rethinking of our philosophy of imprisonment in this country. The main issue in RLUIPA and RFRA suits, as Brother Likko laments, is not whether the plaintiff has a sincere religious belief – that issue is instead largely just presumed to be true. Similarly, it will typically be the case, particularly in the prison context, that the alleged burden on the belief is “substantial,” as all that is required for a substantial burden is that the thing complained-of either be required by the government or the intended outcome of substantial pressure by the government. Instead, the issue in such suits almost always turns on whether the government has chosen the “least restrictive means” for furthering a “compelling government interest.”
Although a “compelling government interest” sounds like a very restrictive and high bar for the government to meet, in practice it is not overly difficult. In the context of prisoner litigation, for instance, the “compelling government interest” test is met by the government indicating its interest in “maintaining order, safety, security, and discipline.” Kikimura v. Hurley, 242 F.3d 950, 962 (10th Cir. 2001); see also Holt, ____ S. Ct. ____ (2014)(noting that prevention of flow of contraband into prison is a compelling interest); cf. Hobby Lobby, 573 U.S. ___ (2014)(presuming government had compelling interest in ensuring access to contraceptives).
As a result, the action in these types of cases will typically be on whether the means of achieving the “compelling government interest” is the “least restrictive” means as applied to the particular plaintiff. This means that the prison official needs to show and argue that imposing the particular policy on the particular prisoner actually serves its purported purpose. He cannot simply say “prison isn’t supposed to be summer camp” and have that be the end of it. He cannot justify the application of the policy on the grounds that it should be viewed as punishment for the prisoner’s underlying crime.
That doesn’t mean that he has to treat the prisoner like the resident of a resort or make prison a pleasant place to live. What he does have to do, though, is show that he treated the prisoner as an individual, not as a mere number. What he has to do is give consideration to why the prisoner is under his stewardship and what is necessary to fulfill that stewardship. What he has to do is show that he’s trying to help the prisoner reform, keep other prisoners safe, and keep the prisoner himself safe.
More importantly, though, he has to actually do these things. Simply and succinctly put: he has to treat the prisoner as an actual human being. While there is no way to entirely get rid of dubious prisoner rights litigation, the fact of the matter is that a prisoner who feels he is being treated like a human being is going to be a lot less likely to find it worth his while to turn to the court system to exact revenge on his warden.
And let us be clear – the dubiousness of inmate claims of religion absolutely pales in comparison to the dehumanizing philosophy that undergirds our prison system. In this system, prisoners are treated as, essentially, automotons – they must wear the same clothes, eat the same food, follow the same routines, etc., risking severe, even more dehumanizing, punishment for any infraction. This dehumanization serves no purpose other than itself. Far from keeping prisoners safe or encouraging prisoners to reform, there is strong evidence that this philosophy pushes inmates into prison gangs. These one-size-fits-all policies that ostensibly exist to make prisons safer seem to have done nothing to deter the extraordinary levels of violence in our prison system. Nor can it be said that the philosophy of dehumanization has been effective at protecting the public from released inmates, given the extraordinary recidivism rates faced in the United States.
Perhaps the solution, instead of imposing dehumanizing one-size-fits-all rules to impose uniformity on prisoners, is to adopt policies that treat prisoners as individuals. And it is these one-size-fits-all rules that RLUIPA suits, dubious as the claims of religion may be, of necessity target, since they specifically seek individualized exemptions from one-size-fits-all policies. If a prisoner wants to wear a green shirt instead of an orange jumpsuit so he can feel like an actual human being, why shouldn’t the warden have to justify the arbitrary orange-jumpsuits only policy?
If the only way to force the warden to make that justification is for the prisoner to find a religion that requires adherents to wear green, why shouldn’t he be allowed to convert – isn’t the belief in one’s own humanity inherently religious even if the specific religion chosen as a vehicle for that belief is a mere pretext? This, after all, is what freedom of religion is really about. It is not about your right to follow the tenets of a particular organized faith. It is about something far more fundamental – even as we use the terminology of “religion,” the freedom, we are in fact discussing is a human being’s unalienable freedom of conscience, quite literally their right to be a human being. As James Madison wrote: “The religion then of every man must be left to the conviction and conscience of every man; and it is the right of every man to exercise it as these may dictate. This right is in its nature an unalienable right.”
The silliness in prisoner claims of religiosity may come across as frivolous even as courts must generally defer to those claims, but the fact is that there shouldn’t even need to be a claim of particular religiosity to vindicate their right to be treated as a human being with a conscience. If it takes some dubious claims as to the religious origin of some beliefs to force wardens to treat prisoners like human beings and to keep the goals of incarceration in mind, then so be it. Even if you’re an atheist, the belief in the right to be treated as a human being ought to reasonably said as bordering on the religious. Given the manner in which prisoners in the United States are treated, we should be less concerned about dubious inmate litigation, and more concerned with making prisons safer, less enabling of prison gangs, and better at helping prisoners reform.
Perhaps an avalanche of RLUIPA suits will leave our prison system with no choice but to change the dehumanizing philosophy under which it operates.
*Though not a religious freedom case, a good example of the types of frivolity often involved in prisoner litigation is one serial litigant’s “Motion to Kiss My Ass.”
**Although Hobby Lobby was not a prisoners’ rights case, the statute under which it was decided, the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, uses virtually identical language as the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act that is the basis for most prisoner religious freedom litigation.
[Post image – Jose Maria Martinez Praying to the Virgin of Remedies of Mexico, 1798, unknown artist]
Would that it will be so, Brother Thompson. But you must count me among the skeptics.
I’ve long shared the opinion that there is no particular reason that prisons must be the violent, dangerous, and dehumanizing places for inmates that they are now; they are thus because someone wishes that they be this way, and the rest of us pretty much don’t care enough about it to stop them from being so. It really doesn’t take a heavy intellectual labor before one realizes that being confined to a prison is bad enough, without adding to the experience the fear of death, assault, rape, and the endless parade of humiliations ranging in scope from the gross to the petty.
There is a strain of political thought leading to the notion that the worse a prison is, the better it is at doing its job. The worse a prison is, greater its power to deter would-be criminals from actually committing their crimes. The worse a prison is, the greater the retribution society exacts when it sends a convict there. So there’s this line of thought that it’s perfectly OK that prisons be violent, dehumanizing places. And it’s sometimes so because of the way the prisons exert their power over the prisoners, other times so because the prisons take a hands-off attitude towards how prisoners behave.
That’s fundamentally inconsistent with the mindset Brother Thompson describes in the OP manifesting as the flower of RLUIPA litigation. But it is something that seems to be embedded in the culture. If it takes a generation of RLUIPA litigation to get people to realize that prisons have a better shot at actually rehabilitating their inmates when they are afforded a degree of dignity on the inside, that’ll be a substantial silver lining to the warp in the fabric of the law which I fear will result from the repeated, public application of religious exceptions to the laws.
I might feel better about all of this if we had either a meaningful way available of really sorting out the sincere from the frivolous religious claims (in the previous thread, @gabriel-conroy asked me about this and I concede that as it stands, no such test has been developed and as a theoretical matter, it’s difficult to conceive of what such a test might be) or if we had some examples of the government meeting its burden under the “super-Sherbert” test found embedded in RFRA and RLUIPA. While the OP is correct that in theory the government can create rules which pass strict scrutiny, and in fact the OP could go further and point out that in other circumstances, the government has a reasonable success rate, in the context of invocation of religious free exercise rights, it’s difficult to find examples of the government prevailing. So we can’t know where the contours of the law really are, which is why I describe the scope of this new standard as seemingly lacking limit.
Better treatment of prisoners makes sense for all sorts of practical as well as moral reasons. I sincerely hope that given the state of the law, this will become one of its beneficial effects. Alas, I cynically doubt that the optimistic prediction of this post will come true.Report
Thanks for the comment, Burt. One point of slight, but important, clarification, if I may:
I don’t think it’s necessary for RLUIPA litigation to get the general population to realize what needs to happen for prisons to function more rehabilitatively. It’s certainly possible that could happen, but I think that by the time such a sentiment took hold, the change in prison philosophy would have already been well under way.
My thinking here is that the prison policies that are so problematic tend to be implemented outside of the legislative process. They’re typically administrative and executive decisions, often on the individual prison level, with which the public usually does not concern itself. There are exceptions, obviously – Sheriff Joe Arpaio comes to mind – but by and large there isn’t much electoral interest in particular prison policies.
Politically, then, changing these policies is not overly difficult (by comparison, changing RFRA and RLUIPA is politically very difficult). Functionally, the obstacle to change is the mindset of prison administrators, as well as the prison guards’ unions, the latter of whom are increasingly being neutralized by the small but vocal and growing movement of evangelical prison reformers.
To the extent that the unions and evangelicals cancel each other out, the decisionmaking of prison administrators is going to be heavily influenced by two very powerful forces: (1) their lawyers; and (2) their accountants. Prison administrators have budgets, and litigation is expensive, especially if you can’t knock it out at the motion to dismiss stage. It’s also time-consuming for the relevant officials if they can’t knock it out at that stage.
My wager is that at some point, prison administrators are going to have to ask themselves just how important it is to them that they maintain these types of dehumanizing policies.
Quickly, regarding cases where the government has met its burden under RFRA and RLUIPA, it will be interesting to see what, if anything, the SCOTUS does about this: http://www2.ca3.uscourts.gov/opinarch/133536p.pdf
The 3rd Circuit ruled in favor of the government on substantial burden grounds, but it seems that their reasoning is identical to how they would rule in favor of the government under a least-restrictive means test.
One other, quasi-related thought that makes me optimistic about broad RFRA-style protections: it will force government to make better policy generally by forcing it to show that applying the policy in a given situation actually accomplishes the policy’s goal. That means that effectiveness must be the sine quo non by which policy decisions must be made. But that’s another post altogether.Report
I’ma read that case in some detail later. Am I right in my quick skim that this is a suit by formal religious entities (I saw at least one RCC archdiocese in there as a party) arguing that even though they can get a contraception mandate exemption under PPACA, even having to fill out the exemption claim constitutes a form of providing contraception, because it sets in motion a chain of events by which contraception is provided to its employees by way of a third party administrator?
(Who pays for that administrator seems to be the relevant question there.)Report
I don’t have much to say on the matter at hand but do want to say how fascinating it is to read you two share an exchange on the matter. Should you ever decide to do a dual post, I’ll be the first to read it. Bravo, @mark-thompson and @burt-likko .Report
First I want to say that this was a thoughtful and thought provoking OP, kudos.
Second, I’ll +1 what Burt said, and maybe even double down. As much as I agree with the sentiment in the post regarding the needlessly dehumanizing conditions in prison, an increase in (perceived) patently frivolous religious lawsuits is just as likely to lead to entrenchment of the status quo, or, possibly, a lessening of the governments burden, so as to lessen the cost to both prisons and court.
I can easily imagine that instead of acknowledging the inherent dignity and humanity of prisoners, when the issue is framed as a cynical plow by prisoners using religion to get special treatment, it will be viewed as another reason to tighten the screws.Report
Well, in large part in defense of the OP, I do think that it is possible for the creation of a legal claim to, over time, mold the culture and actually change peoples’ hearts and minds. The obvious example is Title VII — by putting the power of the courts in the hands of individual litigants aggrieved by certain kinds of discrimination, a broader ethic of anti-discrimination has been created. And it took an entire generation of people growing up never knowing a world other than one in which the courts would step in and correct discrimination in tones of sharp moral condemnation.
Now, RFRA and RLUIPA are not new laws, although their utility and scope has only recently been employed in really powerful, high-profile ways, so in that sense it’s kind of like they’re new. Whether the scope has been meaningfully expanded by recent SCOTUS activity as I see it, or whether all that’s happened is we’re paying attention to what’s been going on all along as Mark sees it, as a political matter, it’s like these are new laws.
So we may be molding a future generation of people for whom the ethic underlying RFRA and RLUIPA are taken as a matter of course, as a relatively unremarkable part of the moral background of how they navigate the world, society, the law, and their faiths. And in some ways, I share Mark’s hope that this could yield some very good cultural results. More freedom, more better.
As I consider the issue more, I realize I didn’t describe another caution, which is that in practice, only mainstream or popular religions will get exceptions and other religions will not. It’s politically easy to grant exceptions to laws that help people who participate in relatively popular religions — letting minors take a little sip of the altar wine at a Catholic Mass, for instance. More unconventional religions will test the limits of peoples’ willingness to tolerate practices they disapprove of generally: sacrificing live chickens in a Santeria ritual, for instance, made the political leaders of Hialeah, Florida recoil in disgust. (OTOH, a lot of people rallied in support of the right of native Americans to smoke peyote.)
Reading this post and mine in conjunction leads me to think, therefore, that the testing grounds are going to be a prisoner practicing one of these non-mainstream religions. While I sure hope the happy outcome Mark predicts here will come true, my money will be going on sooner or later some prisoner doing something that seems edgy to the rest of the world gets granted license to do it and there will be a political backlash that we aren’t going to like very much.Report
“I do think that it is possible for the creation of a legal claim to, over time, mold the culture and actually change peoples’ hearts and minds.”
As do I. I just think a backlash is an equally plausible result to prisoners filing, and the courts perhaps granting, a greater number of frivolous suits, or ones based on exotic religious beliefs.
As Marks argues above, one option for prison administrators when faced with the growing number of lawsuits is to change some of the dehumanizing policies. Another, not mentioned, is for those administrators and guard unions to implement a public relations strategy intended to limit inmate’s use of these statutes, through either restrictive court readings, or explicit statutory change. I find the latter option more likely
Personal experience may also have made me unduly pessimistic regarding our criminal justice system.Report
@gaelen I can’t say that I blame you for your pessimism on this. I’d say in response that there’s one countervailing fact that has recently been emerging that has changed my pessimism into optimism: the rise of evangelical interest and willpower on the issue of prison reform. Conservative evangelicals are, obviously, not the most popular of groups around these parts, and often for good reason. But there really does seem to be some serious passion on the issue of prison reform that has emerged within that segment of the population in recent years. What’s more, they’re well-funded in a way that the prison guards’ union probably can’t be – the political might of the prison guards’ union tends to be a function of its collective bargaining abilities, and ability to mobilize its membership on narrow issues. They also, increasingly, will have to overcome the issue of rising anti-union sentiment on the Right, which is traditionally the group on which they’d need to rely for support on issues they can frame as law-and-order issues (rather than compensation issues).
But it’s probably best for me to frame this as a cautious optimism – your reasons for pessimism are certainly valid and there’s no guarantee the aforementioned countervailing force will prevail or even just neutralize your concerns (which is really all I think may be needed).Report
@mark-thompson
You may well be right. I wasn’t aware of evangelicals changing position before your post, and that could certainly change the political dynamics of prison reform. We can only hopeReport
@gaelen I wouldn’t say they’ve changed positions on the issue – there have been a group of them working on it for quite some time, most prominently Chuck Colson. IIRC, though not an evangelical, Rep. Frank Wolf, who is quite socially conservative, also pushed the issue for decades prior to his recent retirement.
What’s changing is that it’s becoming a higher priority issue within the evangelical community, and one that evangelicals are willing to put some real effort into. I’ve written a lot before about how political coalitions in our two party system are a matter of prioritization of issues and intra-coalition compromises, and that eventually these coalitions become incoherent as some constituents’ high priority items are achieved and de facto compromises on lower priority issues start to be masqueraded as if they were matters of principle.
At some point, as this argument I’ve developed goes, the constituent groups start to ask themselves what good the compromises are doing them for what they actually care about. At some point they start asking what the point of maintaining a coalition and getting power is if they can’t actually seek what’s really important to them without enfuriating another part of the coalition.
That’s what’s happening to the GOP right now, as I’ve been arguing. Part of that is Christian conservatives starting to realize that a lot of what they’re now forced to expend their political efforts on (or at least be silent on) in service of the “three legged stool” of conservatism isn’t terribly Christian and is actively preventing them from expending efforts on things that really are Christian.
Basically, mercy has always been an important element of Christianity. It’s just been an element of Christianity that’s been de-prioritized as a political matter for awhile, though Bush II’s “compassionate conservatism” sought to change that (and very well may have were it not for 9/11).Report
I know that the names of pieces of legislation bare no necessary resemblance to reality (e.g the Patriot Act), but was there supposedly a point at which religious freedom had been taken away and required restoration?Report
According to Congress, yes indeedidilley-eedy. See sections 2(a)(4) and 2(b)(1) of the chaptered legislation to get some good old fashioned (well, actually this sort of thing is relatively newfangled, as laws go) explicit legislative intent. Brother @mark-thompson is quite right to argue that Congress intended a wide sweep and broad application of this law, and so maybe the Courts are just doing what Congress told them to do.Report
I have a hard time believing the RFRA was passed to defend peyote users, or really any religion besides the majority one. So, how were Christians being denied their rights?Report
If Smith and his coreligionists could be prosecuted for smoking a button of peyote in pursuit of their religion, then there was nothing to prevent Catholic priests from being prosecuted for dispensing altar wine to kids during Mass in pursuit of their religion. Nothing save the discretion and forebearance of law enforcement authorities.Report
And the reaction of the people who elect DAs and judges, as well as vote on police compensation packages.Report
@mike-schilling The answer to this line of questioning is, I think, actually quite interesting, and worthy of a full post, though I’m not sure I’ll have time to put it together. But I’ll try to give an abbreviated response here, because I think it says a lot about how politics have changed in the last 22 years, as well as about legislative processes and probably some other stuff too. Apologies if this meanders beyond the scope of your comment, but there’s a lot that’s interesting here.
So here goes:
1. RFRA has obviously become a source of huge frustration and annoyance for liberals, while also being a rallying call for conservatives, because of the Hobby Lobby case. But the Sherbert test that it reinstated when it was passed in 1993 was viewed at the time as somewhat of a cornerstone of liberal jurisprudence. That test came about only after several years of Justice Brennan – arguably the greatest liberal jurist of the 20th century – writing beautiful, passionate minority opinions trying to stand up for the rights of religious minorities. He finally won the battle with his Sherbert opinion, which was a testament to diligence and the power of liberal thought. The Employment Division case undid this completely, and was thus something that understandably would have stirred liberals to action to reinstate what was viewed as an important liberal accomplishment.
2. A couple of years after RFRA was passed, there was a 6-3 decision where the SCOTUS ruled that RFRA could not apply to state laws, but only federal laws despite its language due to federalism concerns (RLUIPA still applies to state prisons, though, because it’s tied to funding). This severely limited the reinstatement of the Sherbert test, since most of the cases where that test had been previously applied involved state laws, including most of the worst abuses that Justice Brennan was concerned about. In the last couple of years, there have been several states that have tried to institute the equivalent of RFRA through their own legislation. To say that liberals have been unreceptive to these efforts would be an understatement – Arizona was boycotted over its attempt to do so, and liberals were ultimately successful in forcing the GOP governor to veto it.
3. There are obviously reasons why liberals have fought so vociferously against state-level RFRA legislation in recent years – namely, the (accurate) perception that the state-level legislation was aimed at undermining anti-discrimination laws and the (probably inaccurate IMHO) perception that it would have in fact done so, but I mention the above just to show how drastically the politics of religious freedom have changed in the last 22 years – a cornerstone of liberal jurisprudence has become a target of extraordinary liberal ire.
4. In 1993, I’m pretty sure that you’d find that the most devout Christian voters were a swing group in a way that they are not currently, and that this trend would have applied across most Christian sects, with the exceptions probably being Mormons and AME. There were still white Southern Democrats – indeed, we had just elected a pair as President and Vice President – but the GOP was well on its way to building its current massive advantage in this group. That made it important for both parties to try to make this group happy.
5. But to get back to your point, why were Christian groups outraged about a decision that protected an AmerIndian religion when Christians were a majority who dictated policy? The answer is that there is no truly dominant sect of American Christianity, and each sect has its own particular beliefs and practices. With evangelicals, the particular beliefs and practices may not even be “organized” in any meaningful way beyond the individual’s personal reading of the Bible. The result is that, while Christianity as a whole may not be likely to be burdened or oppressed by any apparently general laws or rules, any particular sect of Christianity has historically been likely to suffer some kind of burden; often, these burdens have been intentional acts of local government discrimination, as well, as the locally dominant sect seeks to impose its beliefs on the minority sect.
Many, many of the Sherbert era cases involved Seventh Day Adventists (including Sherbert itself), Pentecostals, Jehovah’s Witnesses, or Christian Scientists. While by the time of Sherbert it had become less of a problem, many adherents of the country’s largest Christian sect – Catholicism – had living memory of anti-Catholic discrimination. And of course Mormons have often run into problems where they are not the locally dominant sect.
So that’s why Christians were outraged by the revocation of the Sherbert test, even if it occurred in the context of Amerindian peyote rituals.
The test obviously also provided at least some measure of protection (though not enough in practice as Sherbert was weakened in the years leading up to Employment Division) to non-Christian minority groups, and that protection was, again, a proud achievement in the history of liberal jurisprudence.
So getting rid of Sherbert managed to enfuriate just about everyone. By outright overturning it rather than continuing to chip away at it, Scalia managed to make it a high-profile issue that mobilized religious groups and civil liberty groups across the spectrum. RFRA passed less than three years later, and almost unanimously at that. I’d wager the main reasons it didn’t pass more quickly were that (1) international affairs were dominating in Congress at the time, with the fall of the Berlin Wall, the breakup of the USSR, and the First Gulf War; (2) the decision being a potentially useful extra cudgel in the subsequent Thomas confirmation hearings; and (3) the tremendous unpopularity of the decision, which again was written by Scalia, being a useful campaign issue for Clinton’s 1992 campaign. RFRA was passed just a month and a half after Clinton took office.Report
For whom?Report
People with enough clout to get a bill through Congress.Report
If the people with that much clout are going to benefit, I’m glad they’re benefitting in such a way that the umbrella covers those without.Report