Why They Fight
Jim Manzi has written a provocative post on the moral distinction between battlefield killing and torturing unarmed POWs:
So apparently it’s OK to inflict (the most extreme imaginable) violence when the guy is totally helpless in combat, but suddenly upon his saying the words “I surrender”, any serious violence beyond confinement becomes wrong. Now, the natural justification for this is, I assume, that until he surrenders, if you let him run away, he might very well come back to try to kill you later. Therefore, once you have operationally captured him you are entitled to imprison him for the duration to prevent this future plausible attempt to kill you, but that is all. Why is that all? What changed when he said “I surrender?”. After all, he might escape from the prison camp. It might be your judgment that killing him, or intentionally injuring him short of death while he is imprisoned – as per landmines – might serve your purposes better. One could imagine all kinds of prudential reasons why one might make the judgment that war aims are better served by torturing such a captured combatant. What is the moral reason that you should not pursue such a course of action?
This is an interesting question because it raises so many other issues related to combat, civilian casualties, and the rules of war. Why, for example, are unwilling conscripts routinely subjected to unspeakable violence while high-ranking civilian officials who voluntarily contribute to their country’s war-making ability (and indeed, are arguably more vital to any modern military than an individual conscript) remain untouchable? What is it about putting on a uniform that makes battlefield violence morally justifiable?
I admit these questions are far too weighty for a blog post, but I thought I’d throw out my first intuition. Armies – for better or worse – are battlefield proxies for warring states. They are instruments for winning a war, yes, but they also offer an institutional mechanism for constraining violence. Certain people (soldiers) are acceptable targets for military retaliation. Other people (civilians) are not. This distinction is imperfect and may not always reflect a moral difference (the problem of conscription comes to mind), but identifying certain people as legitimate combatants is one way to ensure the scope of warfare remains (comparatively) limited. The Western tradition of excluding certain classes of persons from combat is actually pretty venerable, with institutional roots dating back to the Middle Ages.
In the case of torture, then, a captured POW is no longer participating in combat and therefore entitled to certain basic protections. This is entirely consistent with the notion of limiting the number of acceptable targets for military retaliation to certain readily-identifiable actors.
This is a prudential, not a moral, judgement. But the larger principle behind this distinction seems morally sound: violence and warfare are terrible, and if conflict is necessary, we should do everything possible to limit the damage to legitimate proxies (soldiers and other voluntary combatants). Since POWs are no longer legitimate combatants, they should enjoy as many protections as we can reasonably afford.
I”m not sure how you define provocative. Manzi seems unaware of any sort of basic ideas of morality. There is a simply a categorical difference between a person who is under our control as a prisoner and person who is not. once they surrender they have stopped being an active combatant and are now our responsibility. Has this guy really thought through the consequences of treating prisoners as people without any moral or legal protections?Report
It’s only a matter of time before Obama has our soldiers armed with rubber bullets.Report
Greginak –
I don’t know, I think there’s some value to throwing out a provocative viewpoint every one and awhile.Report
Will,
So what if the military makes torture a tool of warfare? What if we raise the black flag and commit to violently torturing every captured soldier as a way of breaking the enemy? Does it then become more justifable?Report
Game theory.
If a rational actor sees more of a downside to continuing to fight than he does to waving the white flag, he will wave the white flag.
If a rational actor sees more of a downside to waving the white flag than he does to fighting, he’ll fight to the death.
The question to ask is: What goal are we trying to reach?
If the answer is “genocide”, yeah, surrender is something that you probably shouldn’t take into consideration.
If, however, the answer is *NOT* genocide, you must ask what your goals are and whether your methods will bring you to your goals.
Is your goal to establish a military base? World Peace? To get the survivors of a campaign to shudder when they think of what will happen the next time you get pissed off?
What do you want?Report