Philosophical Defense to the Slippery Slope Argument

Jon Rowe

Jon Rowe is a full Professor of Business at Mercer County Community College, where he teaches business, law, and legal issues relating to politics. Of course, his views do not necessarily represent those of his employer.

Related Post Roulette

6 Responses

  1. Brandon Berg says:

    I don’t think that the 14th Amendment was in any real sense a cause of Obergefell. The Supreme Court has a long history of making decisions on extremely specious grounds. Obergefell happened because a majority of members of the Supreme Court wanted it to happen. If there had been no 14th Amendment, they would have found, or if necessary fabricated, another rationale.Report

    • That’s probably true, Brandon, but how the Court actually reaches its decisions can and sometimes does bind it in certain directions, if only by defining what hoops must be jumped through to decide things a certain way. (I’m drawing off of Stanely Fish’s argument that “the law wishes to have a formal existence. Unfortunately, I don’t have a link, but here’s a brief citation to it: https://books.google.com/books/about/The_Law_Wishes_to_Have_a_Formal_Existenc.html?id=RKk8PwAACAAJ )

      Also, you seem to be assuming that the Court (or the current majority) would *want* to legalize ssm without the 14th and those precedents that relied on the 14th. There’s a historical argument we can make that says the 14th created the one of the hooks–and perhaps also created a set of expectations about equality under (state) law–that people later used to fight for civil rights laws, among which were challenges to miscegenation statutes. A more liberalized approach to marriage choice then led more people to become increasingly favorable to (or agnostic about) ssm. All of which led to creating a constituency in favor of ssm to which the Court, eventually, chose to respond favorably.

      None of which answers what I take to be the criticism of the court implicit in your comment.Report

  2. It’s possible I’m misunderstanding the point you’re making, Jon, but the examples you’re using rely on rules set by the legal system. The law says two types of “cause” have to be established in order for blame to be placed, and within those rules established by the law, a certain form of argumentation works or doesn’t.

    But if we leave the realm of the law, where does that leave us? Let’s say we’re not trying affix blame or trying to create a library of legal precedent to justify a certain decision, but instead are trying to understand how and why something happened. Then the rules aren’t bounded in the same way, whether a cause is only a “cause in fact” or is a “proximate” cause has less importance. In other words, a legal forum establishes certain rules of what counts as truth or good argumentation, and those rules, and not necessarily the rules of logic as Tod and Will debated them in their posts, apply.Report

    • Jon Rowe in reply to Gabriel Conroy says:

      A partial answer to this might be law is a subspecies of philosophy. I’m a trained lawyer, but an armchair philosopher. So that’s the lens through which I often see things.Report

      • Jon Rowe in reply to Jon Rowe says:

        Also, perhaps I’m thinking of Eugene Volokh’s work. He’s way ahead of me in terms of acumen (I think he has an IQ of 200). But his thesis is, however “fallacious” the philosophical concept of a “slippery slope” may be, in law, where we rely on past precedents and reasoning by analogy, it’s there.

        True. But does it have to be. Each time a legal decision is made, you don’t necessarily have to go down the slope. In fact, if you want to, you can go in the other direction.Report